Slow-growing hierarchy

In computability theory, computational complexity theory and proof theory, the slow-growing hierarchy is an ordinal-indexed family of slowly increasing functions gα: NN (where N is the set of natural numbers, {0, 1, ...}). It contrasts with the fast-growing hierarchy.

Definition

Let μ be a large countable ordinal such that a fundamental sequence is assigned to every limit ordinal less than μ. The slow-growing hierarchy of functions gα: NN, for α < μ, is then defined as follows:

Here α[n] denotes the nth element of the fundamental sequence assigned to the limit ordinal α.

The article on the Fast-growing hierarchy describes a standardized choice for fundamental sequence for all α < ε0.

Relation to fast-growing hierarchy

The slow-growing hierarchy grows much more slowly than the fast-growing hierarchy. Even gε0 is only equivalent to f3 and gα only attains the growth of fε0 (the first function that Peano arithmetic cannot prove total in the hierarchy) when α is the Bachmann–Howard ordinal.[1][2][3]

However, Girard proved that the slow-growing hierarchy eventually catches up with the fast-growing one.[1] Specifically, that there exists an ordinal α such that for all integers n

gα(n) < fα(n) < gα(n + 1)

where fα are the functions in the fast-growing hierarchy. He further showed that the first α this holds for is the ordinal of the theory ID of arbitrary finite iterations of an inductive definition.[4] However, for the assignment of fundamental sequences found in [2] the first match up occurs at the level ε0.[5] For Buchholz style tree ordinals it could be shown that the first match up even occurs at .

Extensions of the result proved[4] to considerably larger ordinals show that there are very few ordinals below the ordinal of transfinitely iterated -comprehension where the slow- and fast-growing hierarchy match up.[6]

The slow-growing hierarchy depends extremely sensitively on the choice of the underlying fundamental sequences.[5][7][8][8]

Relation to term rewriting

Cichon provided an interesting connection between the slow-growing hierarchy and derivation length for term rewriting.[2]

References

Notes

  1. 1 2 Girard, Jean-Yves (1981). "Π12-logic. I. Dilators". Annals of Mathematical Logic. 21 (2): 75–219. doi:10.1016/0003-4843(81)90016-4. ISSN 0003-4843. MR 656793
  2. 1 2 3 Cichon (1992). "Termination Proofs and Complexity Characterisations". In P. Aczel; H. Simmons; S. Wainer. Proof Theory. Cambridge University Press. pp. 173–193.
  3. Cichon, E. A.; Wainer, S. S. (1983). "The slow-growing and the Grzegorczyk hierarchies". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 48 (2): 399–408. doi:10.2307/2273557. ISSN 0022-4812. MR 704094
  4. 1 2 Wainer, S. S. (1989). "Slow Growing Versus Fast Growing". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 54 (2): 608–614. doi:10.2307/2274873. JSTOR 2274873.
  5. 1 2 Weiermann, A (1997). "Sometimes slow growing is fast growing". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 90: 91. doi:10.1016/S0168-0072(97)00033-X.
  6. Weiermann, A. (1995). Archives of Mathematical Logic. 34: 313–330. Missing or empty |title= (help)
  7. Weiermann, A. (1999), "What makes a (pointwise) subrecursive hierarchy slow growing?" Cooper, S. Barry (ed.) et al., Sets and proofs. Invited papers from the Logic colloquium '97, European meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic, Leeds, UK, July 6–13, 1997. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lond. Math. Soc. Lect. Note Ser. 258; 403-423.
  8. 1 2 Weiermann, A. (2001) $\Gamma_0$ may be minimal subrecursively inaccessible. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (2001) 397-408.
This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the 10/6/2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.